www.TheLogician.net © Avi Sion - all rights reserved |
The Logician © Avi Sion All rights reserved
|
FUTURE LOGIC©
Avi Sion, 1990 (Rev. ed. 1996) All rights reserved.
CHAPTER 65. DEVELOPMENTS IN TROPOLOGY.
The study of modality on a philosophical plane may be called Tropology
(from the Greek for 'figure', tropos);
it is a broad field, with Ontological and Epistemological ramifications, and a
direct relevance to fields like Aetiology, the study of causality (and thence
Ethics), as well as to the likes of Physics, Biology and Psychology. Modal
logic is a branch and accessory of Tropology, clarifying the formal aspects
and processes of modality.
We have seen in this treatise, that modalities are attributes of
relations (or of any things, in relation to existence). Modalities are
distinguished first with reference to their 'types', and within each type with
reference to their 'categories' (which are similar from type to type). We
dealt in detail with four major types of modality (which may also be more
briefly called 'modes'), which are defined with reference to their 'fulcrums'
— namely, the de-re modalities,
natural, temporal and extensional, and de-dicta
or logical modality. Within each type, we distinguished the categories of
necessity, actuality, possibility, and their negative versions (all of which
have special names assigned to them in the various modes).
The combinations of category with type, yield specific modalities
within each type; but additionally, there are modalities of compound
categories and of mixed types, so that the list of specific modalities is
quite long. Other types of modality exist, like the volitional (a subset of
natural/temporal modality), and the teleological (from which the ethical is
derived, at least in part); but we have not studied them closely in the
present work (though I have myself studied them, and can assert that they fit
into the general scheme here presented).
The fulcrums (or fulcra) of the four modes which here concern us are:
natural circumstances, times, instances of a universal, and logical contexts;
the generic fulcrum is labeled 'cases'. The general definition of modalities
is that they are 'attributes of things or relations which exist
in a number of cases', the number specified determines the 'category' and
the 'type' of cases involved is specified by the fulcrum. For example,
potentiality, or natural possibility) is defined as 'the modality of what is
actual in some circumstances'. All other modalities are defined by similar
statements, mutadis mutandis.
The fulcra are the focal points, the themes, the cruxes, the
frames-of-reference, which distinguish one mode from another. The common
relation is referred to by means of the tiny word 'in' — in some
circumstances, at all times (in all segments of time), in most instances (in
most manifestations of the universal), or in a few contexts, for examples. The
fulcrum frequently has 'boundaries', which delimit the applicability of the
relation; for example, the times or circumstances involved may be those in
which the subject is actual or potential, to the exclusion of those in which
it is not.
The relation of 'in-ness' plays an important role, though it is
notional and intuitive. Its quantitative aspect is explicated spatially, by
analogy to a dot within a larger area (or a point in a circle, say). Its
qualitative aspect is the insight that things are in many cases 'affected' by
their surrounds, that things somehow 'interact' in their environments. Thus, a
wordless reference to causality is involved; but 'causality' at a very vague
and intuitive stage. Later, this notion of causality, which is used to build
up modality from a notion to a scientific concept, is in turn built up into a
scientific concept, by the concept of modality, as we saw.
After such preliminaries, we proceeded with an analysis of the
interdependencies and interactions of the various modalities, with reference
to the oppositions, eductions, and syllogisms between different modalities. At
a subsequent stage, different copulas were also considered. (See part II.)
All this concerns 'categorical' relations, but the concept of modality
gives rise to parallel 'conditional' relations, which in turn further clarify
what we mean by modality. Here, too, we found, we must distinguish between
types of conditioning — the natural, the temporal, the extensional, as well
as the logical (and not only the latter).
For each of the four modes, there exists a variety of conditionings,
distinguished with reference to the 'connection' and the 'basis' intended, as
well as to issues of polarity. There is also a distinction between implicative
conditioning, and various manners of disjunctive conditioning. The connections
and bases were defined with reference to modal (and polar) concepts, and the
logic of their compounds was analyzed in detail. The concept of basis is a
newly discovered one, which refers to the possibilities underlying
a connective actuality. We thus gradually arrived at a greater understanding
of causality. Each type of modality and category of conditioning gives rise to
a distinct concept of causality. (See parts III, IV.)
Lastly, the issue of how modalities are (or are to be) known in
practise, in specific cases arose (which should not be confused with the more
philosophical issue, just mentioned, of how the concepts of modality as such
were constructed). There is of course deduction of modal propositions from
previously identified modal propositions; but ultimately, some modal
propositions have to be induced somehow. We discovered precisely how modal
induction works, in strictly formal terms, through the novel theories of
factorial analysis, factor selection and formula revision (see part VI).
In this way, we developed a pretty thorough theory of modality, which
set terms and methodological standards for Tropology. As far as I can see,
this treatment is original on many crucial counts. Philosophers and logicians
have of course over time done much work in this field. But the present
situation seems to be as follows: a.
the four modes are by now more or less known,
and it is known that they have analogous categories, which are somehow
determined by quantitative issues — but no one so far has arrived at clear
definitions and devised a classificatory understanding of these phenomena; b.
some work has been done since antiquity on modal
syllogism, but errors were made, through failure to take into consideration
the phenomena of change; also, subsidiary matters like productive argument
seem to have been altogether ignored; c.
although logical conditioning has been analyzed
in detail, especially in the modern era, the de-re
forms of conditioning, and of course their respective and interactive
logics, remain essentially unknown to this day; d.
the whole issue of modal induction has never
till now been raised, and therefore of course factorial methods are totally
unheard of.
This is the situation as I found it. A complete history of modality
theory, is beyond the scope of this work. As we have seen, the topic dates at
least from ancient Greece, and crops up thereafter again and again. Here, my
purpose is rather to trace, in a very random-sample and fragmentary manner,
but in somewhat more detail than thus far attempted, more recent developments,
with a view to a fair evaluation of where my colleagues stand today. Also,
comparing and contrasting my thesis, serves not only to defend it, but to
further define it.
My methodology is far from exhaustive: it consists in gleaning
information from a number of works, found in the library of the University of
British Columbia and the Vancouver central public library, having to do with
modal logic. True scholarship would demand a more thorough approach, with a
special concentration on the Big Names in the field: the work of many years.
My spot-checks are not sure to be representative. Such a method may paint an
inaccurate patchwork: it estimates the shape of the whole from points on a
graph.
As earlier stated, I consider Aristotle's understanding of modality to
be broad and profound. The evidence is to be found both in his logical works,
like De Interpretatione and the Prior
and Posterior Analytics, and in his discussions of change, coming into
being and passing away, potentiality, actuality, and natural necessity, and
causality, in works like the Metaphysics,
the Physics, and De Generatione et Corruptione.
Quotations of all his direct or indirect references to issues of
interest to modality theory, would no doubt fill a volume. In any case, what
is relevant to note here is that Aristotle was aware of both the ontological
and epistemological variants and dimensions of modality.
Rescher's Temporal Modalities in Arabic Logic describes the treatments of
natural and temporal modalities found in Arabic texts, such as Avicenna's (Ibn
Sina's) Kitab al Isharat wa-'l-tanbihat
and Averroes' In I De Caelo, which
'are unquestionably of Greek provenience'. It is well known that the historic
value of Islamic Middle-Eastern logic, lay in its bridging the gap of
centuries between the worlds of Antiquity and Christian Europe.
The latter, in its firm will to overthrow paganism, had as it were
'thrown out the baby with the bath water', and indiscriminately rejected some
of the more positive achievements of the old world. Arabic logic, judging from
the said source, concentrated on some of the ontological aspects of modality,
which the Medieval scholars dubbed de re.
Over time, after that, the emphasis (at least in formal theory) shifted to
more epistemological faces of modality, the de-dicta
aspects.
Let us to begin with scrutinize Arab contributions more closely, in the
context of our own theories. First, I would like to say that Arabic modalities
are misnamed when they are called 'temporal', for it is clear that they
are more precisely mixtures of natural as well as temporal modality.
The Arabs had a respectable concept of the various categories
of modality (such as necessity, actuality, possibility, impossibility,
inactuality, possibility-not, contingency), as well as of their interrelations
(a square of opposition was presented by Averroes); but confusions arose when
dealing with the types of modality.
Although they were clearly conscious of the complexities involved, they were
not entirely successful in separating the various issues from each other.
a.
Avicenna distinguishes "absolute" (meaning, unmodalized)
propositions from those which are modalized. However, strictly speaking, this
should be viewed as a grammatical rather logical distinction. In common
discourse, we admittedly do not always explicitly qualify our statements
modally, but from the logical point of view, every proposition has some at
least implicit modality; if the modality is not apparent, then the lowest
possible modality may be assumed, just as an unquantified statement is
considered as particular rather than as a distinct kind of quantity.
Similarly, for so-called "categorical necessity" and
"general possibility", which refer to these categories without
explicit qualification as regards type. Likewise, also, for 'impossibility in
the primary and general sense' and for "special possibility" (by
which is meant, contingency). These were erroneously considered as categories
of a distinct type ("modes"); but they are simply generic concepts,
of unspecified type.
b.
Avicenna does not make clear initial distinctions between natural and
temporal modality, nor between different modalities of subsumption, nor
between the categorical and (de-re)
conditional manifestations of modality, nor between different modalities of
actualization. Instead, the significances of various compounds
of these elements are discussed, as the following definitions make evident:
Thus, "absolute necessity" refers to what is 'in essence
capable of' being predicated of a subject, throughout its duration as such
(even if only in most instances of it or most of the time or in most
circumstances, even if statistically there may be a few rare exceptions). In
contrast, "general conditional necessity" refers to predications
applicable to a subject constantly, while it is in a certain state or it is
surrounded by certain conditions; whereas, "special conditional
necessity" refers to similarly conditional, but temporary events, which
may in turn be "temporal" ('as with an eclipse') or
"spread" ('as with respiration').
Again, "general absolute possibility" refers to events which
are 'not perpetual', yet 'necessary some of the time'. Alternatively,
"general possibility" refers to events which are 'actual at some
times but not others' without being 'necessary at all — neither at a given
time' ("non-perpetual existential") 'nor under certain
circumstances' ("non-necessary existential"). Underlying this
distinction is a concern with the inevitability of actualization, or its
absence, obviously.
We can also see the mixture of considerations in the subdivisions
proposed by Avicenna for actuality: it may be, 'as long as the subject really
exists', "absolute perpetual" (always there, 'but without
necessity') or "general conventional" (there, 'always under certain
definite circumstances') or "special conventional" (there 'at
certain times,… though not perpetually'). Note the appeal to a modality of
subsumption. I will not belabor the topic further: the point is made.
However, one more thing is worthy of note. It is evident (in Rescher's
Table X) that Arabic logicians, if not all past logicians, regarded
first-figure syllogism with a merely possible major premise, whether the minor
premise is necessary or itself possible, as yielding a valid possible
conclusion. Thus, according to them, the modes 1/pnp and
1/ppp (however possibility be interpreted) are valid. This is of
course, as I have shown, a historic error (see ch. 15-17).
Lest the impression have been given that discussions of that period
centered exclusively on de-re modality, I should briefly mention as an example the doctrine
of the Mu'tazilite school of Arab philosophers, who according to A.Y. Heschel
'rejected the idea of causality and taught: What seems like a law to us is
merely a "habit of nature"….' Thus they 'followed the principle
that no heed to is be taken of reality, since it also rests on a habit whose
opposite is equally conceivable'.
To these ideas, the Jewish philosopher Maimonides
replied: 'Reality is not contingent on opinions, opinions are contingent on
reality"' (117). Clearly, what was at issue in these discussions was the
precise relation between de-dicta modality
(the conceivable) and de-re modality
(the real, the natural).
We find in Aristotle an interest in both the de-re
and the de-dicta senses of
modality. In Arabic logic, as we just saw, the emphasis was more on the
former. But thereafter, as we shall now see, European thinkers put more
emphasis on the latter sense. This is already evident in Ockham's discussion
of modal propositions, in the early 14th century. Of course, some logicians,
like J.S. Mill in the mid-19th century, in the context of his study of
causality, continued to focus on modality in a more objective sense.
The tone was perhaps set by the great, 18th century German philosopher Immanuel
Kant who, at the turn of the 19th
century, defined modality in a more subjective sense, as determining 'the
relation of [an]
entire judgment to the faculty of cognition'. He distinguished between
problematic, assertoric and apodeictic judgments; defining these,
respectively, as 'accompanied with the consciousness of the mere
possibility,… actuality,… [and]
necessity of judging' (115). Incidentally, Kant's definitions seem circular to
me, unless possibility, actuality and necessity are defined elsewhere, or
considered obvious notions.
Other influential distinctions were suggested by Kant, among them that
between analytical and synthetic judgements. In the former, the predicate is
'contained [though
covertly]
in the conception' of the subject; in the latter, the predicate 'lies
completely out of the conception' of the subject (Joseph, 207). Again, these
definitions are open to technical criticism, since the terms used in them are
very ambiguous, but that need not concern us here. Kant was apparently trying
to distinguish between the self-evident (which he considered purely 'a
priori') and the empirical.
But Kant's understanding of self-evidence was very naive. For him, a
proposition like 'cats are animals' would be analytical, because 'the
definition' of cats includes that they are animals. But this is an error: such
a statement is synthetic.
When we perceive an object, we distinguish various attributes in it;
perceiving many objects, we find that they have some attribute(s) in common,
and others not in common; lastly, we assign a different name to each distinct
uniformity. Thus, a statement like '(all or some) X are (or are not) Y' signifies: (All
or some of) the things which had the resemblance(s) we labeled "X", also
have (or lack) the distinct resemblance(s) we labeled "Y"
— which may or not also be found in things not having the
resemblance(s) we labeled "X". That 'cats are animals' is therefore
an empirical finding. That 'cats' is a subclass of 'animals', simply means
that all cats are animals, but not all animals are cats (see ch. 44). The
selection of the animal attribute of cats, as essential, as the
defining genus although it is one of many overclasses, may be due to its being
obviously very 'striking' (the automobility of animals is impressively
different from the growth of plants, for instance), or to some logical
intuition based on wider considerations (adductive processes).
In the absence of any deciding factor, the decision may indeed, as a
last resort, be very conventional. Some definitions are admittedly mere word
equations, like 'Bachelors are unmarried men', but even then we always draw on
some underlying experience (in this case, the fact that some men are not bound
to a woman by public vows). Kant evidently focused on a very minor contingency
at the tail of the conceptual process. The same can be said concerning many
later philosophers (and certain modern logicians), who took the more extreme
position that definition is linguistic and conventional. Reasoning is
impossible without some sort of empirical data behind it.
The situation at the turn of the 20th century may be illustrated in the
writings of H.W.B. Joseph, an Oxford logician. His virtue lay in unfettered
discussion of issues, gently bringing many examples to bear, without the
compulsion to quickly and rigidly systematize; I personally learned logic from
his work. With regard to modality, Joseph evidently echoes Kant in focusing on
the distinction between assertoric, problematic, and apodeictic judgments.
Incidentally, he points out that the word 'tropos'
(Greek for 'modality') first occurs in the Commentary
of Ammonius, where it is taken as 'signifying how the predicate belongs to
the subject'. This might be interpreted as widely applying to any adverb; but
logic is more concerned with adverbs which 'determine the connexion'
(according to Michael Psellus), or
more precisely which 'attach to the
copula, and not to the subject or predicate' (according to Buridanus).
Discussing the modal qualifications, Joseph pronounces them 'clearly
logical', but adds that it is not 'the act of judging' nor 'the matter judged'
as such which they concern; rather, they somehow 'mark the distinction between
knowledge and opinion… and differences in certainty'. Judgements not modally
qualified, he calls 'pure'; these as Bain
suggested express mere 'primitive credulity', they are 'assertions… made
without reflection; we do not ask whether they are consistent with others'.
Apodeictic judgment is such that its 'ground… is seen to lie within
the nature of' the terms involved: it is 'self-evident', but that does not
mean that 'it is evident without need for understanding'. Mathematical
statements are not commonly explicitly expressed as necessary, but they all
(those proven) fall in this category. Empiricists 'rightly insisting that
there is no knowledge without experience, wrongly suppose that we cannot by
thinking discover the nature of anything that we have not perceived'. Others,
including G.W. Hegel,
F.H. Bradley, H.H.
Joachim, counter that 'only in apprehending everything could we know
anything as it is'.
Problematic judgment signifies 'our belief of certain facts which are
not sufficient ground for the judgement… though we believe that along with
other facts they would be'. It is 'provoked by knowledge', yet it so qualified
'because of ignorance' (Bosanquet is cited in connection with these insights). Lastly,
assertoric judgment is distinguished from pure, in 'being not a bare
unreflective assertion, but expressing besides our mental attitude towards a
suggested doubt'.
Joseph goes on to say 'these distinctions of modality do not then
express differences in the necessity with which the elements connected in
reality are connected'. He also introduces the concept of probability, as
being related. He concludes: 'what gave modality to a judgment was the
presence of the thought of grounds for what is alleged… the grounds [being]
given in other judgements', so that 'a modal judgement expresses reflection
upon the question of the truth of what is judged or suggested'.
We see here that the initially almost psychological
definitions by Kant, have subtly shifted over into explanations which have
more to do with logic as such.
Modalities (of the type under consideration) are neither entirely subjective,
nor entirely objective, but somehow relate to causal and inductive reasoning
(in the largest sense). We thus return full circle to the 'old distinction
between ratio essendi and ratio
cognoscendi, a reason for being of a fact, and a reason for acknowledging
its being'.
In my own theory of modality, I attempt to contain all these trends.
There are various types of de-re modality,
and there is de-dicta modality, and
the interrelations of the two groups are probed by formal methods. De-dicta
modality is founded in epistemic notions akin to those of Kant, but the
concepts of logical modality as such are more complex constructs. They depend
on an interplay of rational insights, empirical data, and a holistic approach.
A couple of final comments. First, I want to say that, though I respect
Kant highly, as an imaginative and stimulating philosopher, I view him as a
not always very powerful formal logician or practitioner. Secondly, with
regard to Joseph, although his main treatment of modality (188-207) ostensibly
revolves around the de-dicta concepts,
he should not be construed to have at all discarded de-re
concepts.
That is evident for instance in his distinction between disjunctions
which 'express the state of our knowledge' from disjunctions 'in the facts'
(giving as examples 'Plato was born either in 429 or 427 B.C'. and 'Number is
either odd or even'). He was of course in this case referring to the
difference between logical and extensional disjunction. I do not recall
whether he made a similar distinction with regard to implication. But he also
points out that 'X may be Y' in some cases signifies a particular proposition
'Some X are Y', or 'that under certain conditions, not specified, though
perhaps known, X is Y' — here again, the interpretation is factual
(extensional, natural) rather than pertaining to knowledge.
It is also interesting to note Joseph's comment that hypothetical
propositions are often used even 'when we do not see the consequent to be
necessarily involved with the antecedent'. He thus anticipated what I have
called 'lower case' hypotheticals, which only describe a possible consequence
of an antecedent. He also mentions the use of possible disjunctions, as in 'a
G may be either S1, S2, or S3'. It is a pity that other logicians did not
follow up on these observations.
Now to the current century. (The reader is referred once and for all to
Part III of this book, for a fuller discussion of the topics raised here.)
An interesting development was that of 'many-valued' logics, like the
one proposed by Lukasiewicz in 1917. The 'values' under scrutiny were truth
and falsehood — again, purely de-dicta
concepts — and the suggestion was that intermediate values, any number
of them, were conceivable. An example given was 'I shall be in Warsaw in a
year's time', which 'is neither true nor false'; this of course resembles
Aristotle's 'There will be a sea-battle tomorrow'. (Bochenski,
405.)
As I have said before, I have no argument in principle with such an
idea: it is applicable, to the different degrees of credibility or of logical
probability, or even to 'partial truths' (propositional compounds some of
whose elements are true and some false), as well as specifically to future
events conditioned by voluntary factors. My only objection has been that,
ultimately, such logics have to be reducible to the two-valued kind: they do
not displace the latter kind, because it is used to judge their proposals.
That is, we still have to decide, with regard to any proposition of many-valued
logic, whether it is true or false. Modal nuances are not primaries, but
merely quantifications of certain primaries. In any case, many-valued logic
was interesting, as an effort to formally recognize the philosophical truth
that reality and illusion are extremes between which lie uncertain cases. 'Up to 1918 all mathematical logicians — unlike the Megarians, Stoics and Scholastics — used only one notion of implication, the Philonian or material' [ignoring the earlier understanding of implication proposed by Philo’s teacher Diodorus]. At that time, C.I. Lewis 'introduced a new notion of implication and with it a modal logic'. (Bochenski, 403). This refers to 'strict' implication, which was definitely a welcome improvement [or rather, revival] in my view. Lewis clearly brought out the interrelatedness of modality and logical relations.
Note that Frege, not long before, considered modal qualifications to
have 'no place in pure logic'; but H.
MacColl 'had included some suggestions for modal logic' in his work
(Kneale, 548-549).
However, Lewis' modality was only of a logical kind, since its focal
points were the alethic concepts of truth and falsehood; with few exceptions,
this seems to be the main concern of contemporary logic. More importantly, the
relation between these concepts and more stringent concepts such as
'impossibility' was left undefined, with the latter taken as an irreducible
primary. This failure to define the logical modalities, whether impossibility
or any other category is taken as the starting point, plagued modern logic
with manifold problems.
Attempts to effectively define logical modality were woefully weak.
Consider for instance that of Rudolph Carnap in his intricate 1947 symbolic
study of logical modalities, with reference to semantics. His system centered
on necessity; and the 'explicata' he gives for it, which he finds 'clear and
exact' unlike 'the vague concepts… used in common language and in
traditional logic', is as follows:
it applies to a proposition [whose
truth]
is based on purely logical reasons and is not dependent upon the contingency
of facts; in other words, if the assumption [of
its negation]
would lead to a logical contradiction, independent of facts (174).
Look at the description: it is technically no better, indeed much
worse, than most common or traditional 'understandings'. Most of the words
used (like 'applies', 'based', 'logical', etc.) refer to complex modal and
logical concepts, which themselves need to be defined; indeed, many of these
concepts require for their definitions prior definition of modality, so they
can hardly be used to define a modality. Not only is the philosophical
background vague, but the author fails to make an obvious self-test for a petitio
principii.
The impression of rigor given by subsequent symbolic manipulations,
however admittedly 'conventional', is entirely illusory, since no formal rigor
was exercised with regard to the starting points. Apart from such criticisms,
let us anyway note that Carnap was interested, at least primarily, in logical
modality, rather than any de-re concept
of modality.
Instead of seeking definitions, which would conceptually explain the
accumulated intuitions of logical science, in the way of a theory to cover the
facts — Lewis and those after him used certain known logical phenomena as axioms
from which the others were to be derived, following the model of the Principia
Mathematica. Consider, for instance, the axioms of Lewis' modal system S1.
One 'axiom' was that a proposition implies the negation of its own
negation, or that 'P' implies 'not nonP'. For me this is not an axiom. The law
of contradiction, as I have argued at length, cannot strictly-speaking be
construed as a general first premise from which others are deduced; rather, it
must be viewed as an inductive summary of countless specific logical insights.
A fact and its negation never occur together in our experience; or if they
seem to, that event itself is experienced as somehow faulty and needing some
sort of correction. The word 'not' merely labels such phenomena; it does not
invent or create them.
Likewise, some of the 'axioms' relate to the logical relation of mere
conjunction, for instance that 'P and Q' implies 'Q and P' or even just 'P'
and just 'Q'. For me these are not axioms. We commonly 'experience' situations
where two or more propositions all seem true in a context. The word 'and' is
used to refer our attention to such situations. It is evident from
the experiences we intend by it, that the 'togetherness' is a
nondirectional relation and does not exclude separate existence (had we
experienced something else, we would have said so).
Such underlying experiences can be, and often are, wordless;
the words (or symbols) cannot therefore be regarded as conventional
determinants. The relation of implication cannot in any case be used to define
'not' and 'and', because it is itself much more complex than them, and anyway
(as it turns out) they are required to define it.
All that these so-called axioms do is report
what we commonly and invariably all intuit: they do not serve to justify
these intuitions, which are primary givens. If they are neither 'conventions'
nor definitions nor first premises, then it is misleading to call them axioms.
All the more reason, propositions like 'if P implies Q and Q implies R,
then P implies R' (the primary mood of hypothetical syllogism) and 'if P
implies Q, and P is true, then Q is true' (the primary mood of logical
apodosis), cannot be characterized as axioms. They cannot be placed, as Lewis
and others have done, at the fountainhead of logical science. They are only at
all meaningful provided we first come to an understanding of logical
modality, which would allow us to define implication in such a way that,
indeed, these properties emerge.
Similarly, that 'possibly{P and Q} implies possibly P and possibly Q',
is a very derivative propositions, which depends for its recognition on a
preceding understanding of logical modality. Once we know that possibly means
'in some contexts', it is easily seen
that if 'there are contexts where both P and Q seem true', then 'there are
contexts where P seems true and contexts where Q seems true, and some of those
contexts at least are the same'. Likewise, that 'there exists cases where P
neither implies Q nor implies nonQ' is a common observation: some propositions
seem unrelated to each other.
In each case, we have an appeal to the idea of subsumption;
or, if you wish, to the topological principle that the whole is made up of and
includes the part. But even here, the relation involved is repeatedly intuited
as 'logically forceful'; our statement of it is a mere verbalization of information, and not the source of our
conviction.
Additionally, we must distinguish the intuitive notion
of implication, reflecting our experiences of one thing seeming to lead to
another, from the more conceptual construct
of implication, defined with reference to modality. For this reason, we can
make statements like the above, reporting common logical experiences, even
before we have proposed a theory as to the definition of implication (with
reference to modality). Common intuitive knowledge (what we call 'common
sense') is used to test and tailor the eventual definitions.
All this to say: such 'axiomatic systems' grossly
oversimplify the conceptual complexities involved in logical concepts.
They fail to pay attention to what might be called the genealogy
of the ideas involved. One cannot avoid having to define the logical
modalities, and they are not definable arbitrarily. There is a step by step
process, layer upon layer: a.
first, we have specific intuitions and
experiences of the kind we label 'logical', about various things; b.
notions are formed about these logical
phenomena: they are pointed to, distinguished from each other, and variously
named; c.
regularities in behavior are faithfully observed
and duly recorded: these will serve as the database for subsequent theorizing; d.
concepts can now be formed, which are capable of
embracing the said regularities: such construction itself involves reliance on
ad hoc logical insights; e.
only finally, do we have complex logical
principles, to play around with symbolically, and order into axioms and
theorems: and even these actions depend on the intuitive experience of their
logical 'rightness' or lack of it.
The issues are further complicated by the fact that the progressive
developments of different ideas impinge on each other at different stages of
the proceedings. The logical intuitions and notions concerning them all
come into play at all stages of each
concept's development; and additionally the concepts are tiered relative to
each other. We have therefore to zigzag from one idea to the other; there is
no way to hierarchize whole
sequences.
Thus, at the lowest level, we have: appearances, their apparent
credibilities, their apparent impacts on each other, their apparent
contextuality. Next, the concepts of truth and falsehood are defined, by
comparing the seeming credibilities of seemingly opposite appearances in a
given context. Next, modal concepts, like necessity or possibility, are
defined with reference to numbers of contexts in which truth or falsehood are
found. Next, logical relations, like implication, are defined, by modalizing
conjunctions and their negations. At the highest level, probabilities can be
analyzed, with reference to all the preceding.
Let us now consider the kind of proposition modern logicians considered
as optional axioms or as theorems worth
deriving; specifically, we shall consider the doctrine of 'orders of
modality'.
Many different 'modal systems' were proposed by Lewis and others,
according to which established logical principles were taken as primary: if p
implies q and q implies p, then either of p and q can be taken as more
primary. That assumption ignored conceptual considerations, as already made
clear. Also, certain logical relations are ab-initio
of undetermined value: therefore, different systems could be constructed, by
arbitrarily assuming an additional proposition or its negation as one of the
axioms. Thus, what is an axiom in one system might be denied in another, or it
might be derived in the way of a theorem.
A great fascination arose with one kind of question especially: that of
'superimposition of modalities'. Starting with O.
Becker (according to Feys),
logicians like Lewis, Carnap, Godel, Von Wright, McKinsey,
Parry, debated it with the utmost
seriousness.
They called logical categories like necessity and possibility 'first
order' modalities; their reiterations were called 'second (or higher) order'
modalities. This refers to verbal constructs like 'necessity of necessity' or
'possibility of necessity', and similarly in other combinations. The questions
they asked were: Does necessity imply necessity of necessity, or what? Does
possibility imply necessity of possibility, or perhaps possibility of
necessity, or maybe possibility of possibility? (Why not necessity of
necessity, for that matter?) These were called 'reduction principles'.
Carnap, for instance, claimed to demonstrate, on purely semantical
grounds, that necessity implies necessity of necessity (174-175). In view of
the controversies, the Kneales, in 1962, wondered 'if it is not possible [to
resolve such queries]
how shall we ever be able to settle the question? What sort of evidence should
we seek and where?' (556).
But, I say, once a quantitative definition of the logical modalities
has been constructed, these questions appear utterly puerile. If the
reiterated categories in question are of uniform modal type, that is, all de-dicta,
logical concepts — the answers easily proceed from purely quantitative
considerations. 'All of all the contexts' is equivalent to 'all the contexts'
(necessity). 'All of some', 'some of all' and 'some of some' of the contexts,
all signify 'some of the contexts' (possibility), although their precise
extensions may well vary.
Admittedly we commonly do repeat modal qualifications. But often, the
intent is only to emphasize, a mere linguistic flourish: I am sure that I am
sure, I am unsure that I am sure, and so forth. Sometimes, perhaps, we intend
a sequence: I am still sure, I am no longer sure, and so on. Such statements
tell us whether a verification has or has not taken place, and whether further
research is or is not called for.
Knowledge and opinion, as we have seen, vary over time, in the
transition from context to context; thus, assumed (that is, contextually
imposed) modalities do change, and logical science may have an interest in
analyzing such changes in precise detail. But in its essence, logical modality
is a static phenomenon: we are not so much interested in the history of our present modal
qualifications, but rather in specifying how the present context is
determining them.
Thus, the logical modality of a logical modality is not in practise
meaningful: the weakest component determines the whole. In any case, such
issues cannot be construed as having so much importance in modal logic that
they may play an axiomatic role, even optionally.
The only significant way such nestings of categories of modality occur
in practise, is when the categories are of mixed
modal type. Concepts like 'the logical necessity of a natural necessity'
are quite legitimate. In this example, we are asking whether the proposition
concerned is not only naturally necessarily but logically so; I believe, in
this case, the reply to be that logical necessity implies natural necessity,
though a natural necessity may well not be logically necessary.
Any mix of logical, natural, temporal, and extensional modalities can
similarly be considered. My analysis of compound, fractional and integral
modal propositions is intended as an
exhaustion of all the combinations of natural, temporal and extensional
modalities with each other, for categorical propositions. Logical modality
is not included, because the other modalities are viewed as the ultimate
objects of study; they are the goal, logical modality is only a means (ch. 51,
52).
But in practise, we should not rush to judgment, for the intent is
often more complex than it seems. Thus, taken simply, 'X must always be Y' is
redundant, since 'must' implies 'always'. But the intent may rather be that,
each time 'X is Y' actualizes, it does so inevitably
(rather than spontaneously or voluntarily). Likewise, 'X can sometimes be
Y' may be simply viewed as an abbreviation of the compound 'X can and
sometimes is Y', or in more clever ways. Such statements may also be intended
to refer to acquisitions or losses of
powers. (See ch. 34.3, 51 for introductory comments on these topics).
The issue is never verbal or grammatical or symbolic. Words do not
affect the issue: what matters to logic is what we intend by them. It makes no
difference whether we say 'It is necessary that X is Y' or 'X is necessarily
Y' or 'That X is Y is of necessity true', contrary to what the Kneales suggest
(553). It makes no difference whether 'must' refers to 'logically must' or
'naturally must' or 'always' or 'all', so long as we agree on a terminology:
we all have access to the underlying concepts, anyway.
In any case, note, logicians cannot analyze such mixed-type stacks of
modalities in a generic way, because for all we know to start with, different
combinations may have different explanations. Some general rules might emerge
as a final conclusion; but they should not be predicted offhand. The issue is
complicated by the interrelations of modal types, which are not entirely
continuous (see for instance ch. 38.2).
Logical modality differs radically from the de-re
types, in that it concerns a different domain, that of 'contexts', instead
of that of 'circumstances' or 'times', or again that of 'instances'. Yet
logical necessity implies the natural and temporal, and natural and temporal
possibility implies the logical, in categorical forms (ignoring issues of
modality of subsumption). However, in conditioning, these continuities are
inhibited, because logical forms have been designed as mere connectives,
whereas de-re forms must have a proper basis.
Natural modality likewise surrounds the temporal, but
their categorical continuity is broken in conditional frameworks, because
of their different bases. Again, extensional modality stands somewhat apart
from the natural and temporal, since it concerns groups rather than
individuals. (See ch. 25, 34, 38, 39).
We find reference to the 'resemblance to quantity' of logical modality,
in a 1962 book by A.N. Prior. Again, the focus is on that specific type of
modality — 'assertoric', 'apodeictic' and 'problematic' are the words used
for its categories (185). But in any case this shows that the analogy of
logical to extensional modality, which was obvious since antiquity (with
reference to the oppositions of modal categories and to modal syllogism), was
acknowledged in modern times.
However, this analogy is useless without a significant explanation: the
quantitative aspect in the logical modalities can only be brought out by
defining them. The given datum of similar logical behavior between modality and
quantity, should have been seen as a
clue to some essential similarity: it was a missed opportunity for
constructing a fitting definition of the modalities.
Robert Feys suggests that, already in the 19th century, 'it would have
been rather natural that the calculus of propositions be conceived as… a
modal one' in analogy to the 'calculus of classes'. Because, 'propositions
were conceived as applicable to (verified in) various "cases",
"circumstances"", "moments of time", "states of
affairs"', so that 'an implication was a proposition asserting that all
cases in which p is verified are also cases in which q is verified' (3).
This statement shows that, at least at the time it was written, in
1965, logicians did indeed come very close to a precise, quantitative
definition of modality and conditioning, at least in a generic sense (if we
take the latter use of the expression "cases" at its broadest). But,
on second thoughts, the statement seems more intended to define the
form-content relation, rather than the modal underpinning of implication.
In any event, as far as I know, modern logicians did not explicitly
work out distinct modal and conditional logics for each of the types of
modality implied by the words they used. They should have taken, as I did,
"cases" (in a narrow sense) as the focus for an extensional logic,
"circumstances" as that for a natural one, "moments of
time" for a temporal one, and "states of affairs" (in the sense
of knowledge contexts) for a logical one. For, when one does so, it becomes
clear that these various logics have distinct (though parallel) properties,
which justify their separate developments. My impression is that they lumped
all types together, and considered the logical sense to be generic.
This impression is not entirely offset by, for instance, Rescher's
listing of many types of modality, including the 'alethic' and 'likelihood'
(logical), the causal (natural), the temporal, the deontic and evaluative
(ethical). For, though it is clear that he is aware that there are varieties,
he also lumps such intentional relations as 'believing' and 'hoping' into the
list, showing that he is not aware of the characteristic pattern which defines
a relation as modal. One may well argue that such attitudes are determined by
modal judgments, but they are not themselves modal (White, 168).
Questions posed by Feys concerning modality reveal the state of
knowledge of current logicians; he asks if it can be used 'for the description
of the physical world', or 'perhaps… in the analysis of causality'. I infer
that they had not yet formally treated the relations between logical and de-re
modality, and had not yet developed the logic of de-re
conditionings.
It is also interesting to note that modern logicians seem still
disturbed by the existence of paradoxical propositions (like p implies notp,
or notp implies p). Thus we find the Kneales complaining about the lack of
success of logicians 'in excluding these so-called paradoxes without also
excluding at the same time arguments which everyone regards as valid' (549).
Again, had they had good definitions in mind, they would have seen that
there is no antinomy in such statements provided they occur singly, not in
pairs. On the contrary, precisely the existence of paradoxical forms allows us to define the
concepts of logical necessity and impossibility, as self-evidence (a
proposition implied by its negation) and self-contradiction (a proposition
implying its negation), respectively.
Let us now look at how a recent (1976) Dictionary
of Philosophy discusses modalities. It focuses on 'alethic' modalities;
these include the necessity or possibility 'of something being true'; the
'factual' is defined as neither necessary nor impossible nor merely possible.
But such a definition is admitted to be circular: 'it is hard to define modal
terms without begging the question'.
A statement without explicit
modal qualification is called 'assertoric'; only if the
word 'necessary' or 'possible' appears in it may the statement be called
'apodictic' or 'problematic'. The author, A.R.
Lacey, admits that 'Kant uses "apodictic", etc. slightly
differently to indicate how judgments are thought, not expressed'.
But this difference is far from 'slight', it is a still more massive
confusion of the issues. Whether or not certain words are used, the logical
status of the proposition is not affected; moderns do not seem to understand
that. We could say that the words used indicate whether the maker of a
statement is aware or not (or wants to stress or ignore) its logical modality.
But, as far as logical science is concerned, within
the context of knowledge of that person, the logical modality of the
proposition is determinate, whether known and stated or not.
Admitting that 'modal logic… is not always limited to the alethic
modalities', the article goes on: 'a difficult and controversial distinction,
of medieval origin, is that between de re
and de dicta modality', applying the former 'to the possession of an attribute
by a subject' and the latter 'to a proposition'. Some 'view that de re
modality is intelligible, and that there are cases of it, even if
ultimately they must be analyzed in terms of de dicto modality', while others
deny this view in some way.
Further on: 'the nature of physical necessity and possibility has been
disputed for centuries, especially since Hume. Are they independent of logical
necessity and possibility, or ultimately reducible to them, or merely
illusory?' Also: 'can there be possibilities which remain possibilities
throughout all time but are never actualized? Aristotle and Thomas
Hobbes, among others, said no'.
It is suggested that the
logically or physically necessary may be 'what happens… in all conceivable
worlds or all worlds compatible with certain laws', though admittedly the
words '"conceivable" and "compatible" have modal endings'.
(Incidentally, Bradley and Swartz seem
to attribute this suggestion to Wittgenstein (7), but as I recall the phrase
'all possible worlds' dates from Leibniz; in any case, such a phrase obviously
cannot be used as a definition of possibility.)
I think that the results presented in my book adequately answer all
these questions. The fact that they (and others like them) are still asked, in
so recent an article, tells me that similar results have not been obtained by
others. The objectivity and scientific knowability of natural modality is
demonstrated by my formal theory of modal induction.
Natural necessity may be deduced from logical necessity (or of course
from other natural necessities), or
induced by generalization (according to strict rules) from actuality or
potentiality, or even logical possibility (by adduction); actuality is observable,
as well as inferable deductively or inductively; potentiality may be deduced
from actuality or necessity, or be
discovered indirectly by syllogistic means (from other potentialities), or
even induced from logical possibility (as a last resort, by adduction). And so
forth: these issues are easily resolved, very formally, once the categories
and types of modality are clearly defined.
It might be contended that I am being too picky, in evaluating modern
understanding of modality. Are my definitions of the modalities so far
different from the current ones? For instance, Paul
Snyder of Temple University, in 1971, writes: 'Alethic modality is
concerned with what must be the case in every
possible state of affairs (necessity) or in some
possible state of affairs (possibility)'. Is that so different from my own
proposals in ch. 21?
The point is well-taken. The quantitative aspect of logical modality is
by now, in Snyder, clearly brought out. The choice of words 'must
be the case that' and 'possible
state of affairs', may be excused, as not a circularity but a parenthetical
emphasis. 'State of affairs' is equivalent in intent to what I call 'context'.
It is sufficient to remark that 'while contexts exist (mentally or
perceivably), they are actual';
there is no need to say that they are 'possible'. I am open, but still at
least insist on my own wording.
The necessary is that given in all contexts of knowledge, the possible
is that given in some. We do not need to specify that some of the contexts are
merely 'possible', because that is understood from the awareness that contexts
change across time and from person to person, that is, that there 'are' (in
the widest, timeless sense) actual contexts other than here and now. And of
course, it is important to stress that the environments concerned are (in the
widest senses) empirical and logical data, that is, items of 'knowledge'.
Indeed, sticking with Snyder, we can regard the idea that there are
many 'systems' of (modal) logic with more generosity. He says, provocatively,
'There is not precisely one correct system of logic. There are many'. But
later he makes clear that by that he means alethic modal logic, temporal
logic, deontic logic, and so forth. Some rules hold 'generically
for all the senses of "necessary" and "possible"', while
'some features… will not be shared' for instance by logical and physical
modality.
Again, I cannot but congratulate and agree. I also subdivide modal
logic into various 'types' (the extensional, the natural and temporal, the
logical, the ethical), each of which has to be treated as a separate field,
because of their distinct properties, though eventual parallelisms do emerge.
Note again that I do not regard tense as such, nor knowing and believing, nor
intending, willing or preferring, or the like, as 'modalities' in a strict
sense, but as considerations which may underlie modal concepts (which are
distinguished by quantification of certain phenomena).
One example of distinct properties of modal types is paradox. We have
seen that logical conditioning need not be based on logical possibility; here,
a de-dicta connection without basis,
that is, based only on problemacy (a mere mental consideration of the theses)
is quite thinkable; and paradox may therefore arise. In contrast, de-re
conditioning must be based on the corresponding de-re
possibility; a de-re connection
without a corresponding basis does not exist (or more precisely, is too
formal), and problemacy does not suffice; for this reason, there is no
equivalent of paradox in de-re logic.
You could say that we design our forms of conditioning, in such a way as to
avoid such embarrassments on a de-re level,
and keep them on a logical level. But in any case, the logics of de-dicta and de-re conditionings
end up looking rather different.
In my view, in any case, it is misleading to call these fields
'systems', because that would suggest relativistically that there are many
Truths. That each type of modality has distinct properties implies nothing of
the kind, anymore than saying that 'cats and dogs behave in disparate ways'
would do so. However, Snyder's statement does in fact proceed from the modern
approach we have already noted, that according to the 'axioms' we more or less
arbitrarily adopt, radically different complete systems of logic emerge, which
may or not find practical application. For this reason, he adds that there are
'literally hundreds of distinct systems of formal logic'. With such attitudes,
I cannot agree.
In my view, generic logic sets the common 'axioms'; the subsidiary
'axioms' serve for purposes of specification. There are no systems which
qualify as logical, outside the general framework of laws like
non-contradiction; special fields of logic merely add additional laws of their
own. The perverse delight of relativism is not serious, and should be avoided;
the logician is dedicated to strengthening common sense, not to try and debunk
it (since that is in fact impossible, as repeatedly shown).
I also cannot accept the modern view, which is a direct consequence of
such extreme axiomatism, and more deeply of conventionalist interpretations of
language — that, once the axioms are declared, the theorems follow
relentlessly, to quote Snyder: as 'a straight-forward mechanical procedure…
that could just as well be done by a computer (and, as a matter of fact, has
been done by an IBM 7074)' (1-12).
The work of logicians can never be divorced from philosophical
considerations. Logic is inextricably interwoven with epistemology and
ontology; the three evolve in tandem, stimulating inquiries in each other,
mutually informed and informing. The directions taken by logical science
result from a mass of insights into the world and our knowledge of it.
The totality of primary
propositions required to develop a mechanical model of logic, is far greater
than a few limited 'axioms': it is an innumerable number of experiences and
intuitions related in very complex ways. The attempt to ignore that
subtext is a sad falsification.
At every stage in the development of any theory of logic, one is called
upon to consider countless, interrelated philosophical issues. The success of
the theorist depends mainly on his ability to resolve such issues with vision,
with the broadest regard for available data. There are some
points in our progress, from which a series of developments follow more or
less mechanically. But even then, the logician must be present, to determine
what is relevant to human experience; to test, modify or reject. All a
computer, which has no consciousness, only symbols of data (whether fed by
humans or robotically acquired), can do, is duplicate the said mechanical
segments of logic's growth.
The validation of logic is a function of a large number of insights.
The reordering of the propositions formed
from these insights, in accordance with the model of axioms and derived
theorems, is perhaps an interesting and worthy research, but it is an
auxiliary and ex-post-facto
development. To suggest, as modern logicians do, that a dozen or a score of
'axioms' suffice to construct a logical system from scratch, is ridiculous.
Apart from that, we may severely doubt that the 'axioms' they propose
are all indeed primary propositions. Most are certainly not
conceptually primitive, but in practise and in theory the end-products
of very significant preliminary, philosophical positionings, whether conscious
or effective. This does not mean that logic is a derivative science, but only
that its mental separation from philosophy is an artifice; the two are part of
and depend on each other.
The more geometrico concept is itself an outcrop of logic and cannot be
regarded as validating it; rather, logic confirms it for us, and encourages us
in its use thenceforth. Logic develops from innumerable individual experiences (in the largest sense), including perceptual
and conceptual insights, and intuitions
of logical correlation, that we call consistency, conflict, implication or
alternation. Intellectual validity is merely a subset of notional validity.
The geometrical model emerges from the theory of adduction, not from
purely deductive motives. The perceptual and conceptual insights may be taken
for what they are, or eventually grouped into forms; the logical intuitions
may be taken ad hoc, or generalized into logical science. The 'common sense'
art of logic, is the parent, not a poor cousin of the science. As the patterns
of our inductions emerge, we come to see the value and importance of deductive
ordering of the information into 'axioms and theorems', as a final step and a
test. But the validity of the whole stems from the roots.
The relation of logical science to logical practise is not merely one
of consistent one-way implication — in the manner, say, that physical
theories relate to their predictions. That adductive relation is indeed
visible, after the fact; but it is two directional. Not only is logical
practise generalized into logical science, but logical intuition demands that
we admit logic to be the only
framework suitable to our experiences. It is more than just a
theory with fitting predictions: it is the sole theory acceptable to logical
intuition. The deductive inference of theorems from axioms depends on this
notion, and cannot therefore be used against it.
I find myself in closer agreement with the views of Alan
White, of Hull University, expressed in his 1975 study of modal thinking.
He analyzes common usage of modal qualifications, discussing what we
ordinarily mean by them with reference to examples, and arrives at very
balanced and intelligent conclusions. His style reminds me much of Joseph's:
perhaps there is a British way; in the case of White, three quarters of a
century of modern subjectivism and linguisticism have intervened, but the good
sense he brings to bear is characteristic (165-179).
The views held by some, that modalities express 'some subjective
feeling or mental experience… of compulsion… or confidence', or 'the
attitude or mood' qualifying our assertions, are rejected by White. His
argument is that the alternatives are not either some such thesis, or a naive
objectivism, according to which the modalities are grossly physical — but
there is a position in between, a more nuanced objectivism.
Cases in point are, the argument of the great, 18th century British
philosopher David Hume, with regard
to logical necessity and also to 'causality' (meaning natural necessity), to
the effect that 'since there is no ostensive quality or object called
"necessity",… [it]
must be the name of something subjective', and similarly that of Ludwig
Wittgentein, in the present century, that '"essential" is never the
property of an object, but the mark of a concept'. Note that in the latter
case, the relevance of the statement proceeds from the Kantian position that
necessity is a property of definitional predicates; but of course
Wittgenstein's emphasis is more linguistic.
For White, 'if anything is modally characterizable, it is so because in
a certain situation in terms of alternatives relative to a given end… and
viewed under a certain aspect (e.g. physically, logically…), it is open
(can, may, possibly)… or is the only one (necessary, must…). In short,
modal concepts do not signify particular items either in the world or in our
minds, but the relation of one item to others in a situation'. The 'relative
nature of the modals' (he also uses the word 'contextual'), allows for 'an
objectivity free from traditional objections'. What is so nice to see, is
White's firm conviction that logicians who do not arrive at some sort of objectivist conclusion, have
simply failed to answer the question.
This is my view, too, that modality is a relational qualification,
which is objective, not in the sense that it is concretely perceptible, but in
the way of an abstract existent which is apprehended by conceptual means. The
choice is not merely between mental or verbal inventions, and sensory
phenomena; we may also, through direct intuitions (on a notional level), or
indirectly by the accumulated constructions of such intuitions (on an
intellectual level), arrive at an insight of realities, which are just as
objective as sense data. The abstract is simply another kind of phenomenon
than the concrete, but equally 'empirical'. I have shown justifications for
this view in ch. 60-62; I need not repeat them.
White is also concerned about the modern interpretation of the old de-dicta/de-re
distinction. For logicians like Russell, Rescher, Von Wright, all types of
modality qualify whole propositions, and are 'therefore' de-dicta
(suggesting that they are not objective, as already said). White rejects
the conclusion, saying 'there is no such thing as modality de dicto…
different modals… can all be classed as de re'. (in the sense that they are
objective, in the way of descriptions of relational phenomena, as just seen);
but he goes on to infer that they do not qualify propositions as such.
Here, I slightly disagree with him, but the differences are
inconsequential and verbal, rather than fundamental. I agree that even logical
modality, let alone the natural other such types, is essentially objective. It
does not, however, follow that we may not regard modal concepts as qualifying
propositions, in the sense of their contents (rather than as utterances). He
is contraposing an incorrect hypothetical.
I favor retaining the de-dicta/de-re names, to stress an important difference. Logical modality
appeals to a maximal context, which includes constructs granted as fictional, as well as presentative data of a perceptual
or conceptual kind; whereas modalities like the natural, arise in more
limited frameworks, to the exclusion of known fantasies. Thus, we have
good reason to make a differentiation, even while acknowledging the equal
objectivity of results obtained in all these fields.
For me, the concept of modality refers essentially to degrees
of being. At first, the 'is' copula appears to have a single,
straightforward sense: this is the 'is' of indicative
propositions, referring to singular, actual, now, true, events. But as we
proceed with the enterprise of knowledge, we grasp that there are nuances in
this concept. In some cases, the relation is very finite, in others, it has a broader frame of reference.
It may be more 'forceful': general, independent of circumstance, timeless, free of
the influences of phenomenal changes; or it may be more 'open': particular, potential, temporary, imaginable. In this
manner, the need for concepts of necessity and possibility emerge, as stronger
or weaker versions of the primitive
concept of mere presence. Likewise, needless to say for the negative
equivalents (and similarly also, incidentally, for ethical value judgements,
except that they involve still more complex relational issues).
These (pre-scientific) notions of other levels of being, are eventually
formalized, in such a way that their hierarchies are made evident, and rules
for their induction are developed. This additional layer of
intellectualization (the science of logic) is what gives the modalities an
appearance of being propositional qualifications, but they essentially concern
the content. Mental processes leading to their acceptance as justified
knowledge are incidental; what counts is the final status they deserve.
Incidentally, in reply to Hume: it is clear that the causal notions of
force or openness are pre-verbally implicit in the notions of modality, but
their formal elucidation is a later stage. First, modality is applied to
single predications; then, to their conjunctions; finally, after the various
types of conditioning have been studied, we can begin to study causality, in
its various senses (see ch. 33.2, 42.2). Also, in reply to Wittgenstein: the
fact that we are free to focus or not, on different aspects of things, does not imply that
what we have any choice over what we thereby become aware of; the contingency
of consciousness does not signify contingency for its objects.
A contemporary writer on issues relating to modality, who seems to be
quite prolific and distinguished, is Jaakko
Hintikka, of Helsinki and Stanford Universities. He also, like White, is I
would say a philosopher, rather than a mere logician, in his approach to
modality. I do not agree with every detail of his views, but his overall
attitude that the battleground for modality is in the wider neighborhood of
epistemology and ontology, is refreshing.
Thus, we find Hintikka saying, in a 1969 essay on epistemic logic, 'the
usual straightforward axiomatization of the logic of philosophically
interesting concepts is likely to be a worthless enterprise unless it is
backed by a deeper analysis of the situation'. A similar guideline has always
controlled my own theorizing.
Hintikka criticizes not only symbolic logicians, but also those
'ordinary language analysts' who engage in 'mere description of the raw data'
of ordinary language; he calls for a 'genuine theory of the meaning of the
words and expressions involved'. Of course, that criticism is not applicable
to all ordinary language analysis; Hintikka engages in some himself (also,
incidentally, White's analysis does not have this fault, in my view.) I will
use this essay as a springboard for certain remarks (3-19).
When we scrutinize examples (or 'paradigms'), with a view to
understanding both their epistemological determinants and their ontological
content, our aim is not a mere 'summary of the data' of common practise, a
descriptive generalization. If logical science consisted merely of summaries
of our linguistic habits, it could not have any prescriptive role.
Rather, we select those cases which seem most significant, and by
adduction formulate a theory around them, which is then worked out in formal
detail. Such seminal and pivotal concepts acquire a normative character, not
in the way of an artificial imposition (or 'regimentation'), but because they all
together suffice to eventually construct and explain all less important
cases.
Thus, when we reserve the word 'can' to one of its senses evident in
common practise (namely, potentiality), we do not thereby exclude all the
other senses, but intend to later deal with them, either as subsidiary senses
or using other words. If an ordinary use of 'can' is not included by our rigid
definition of the word, we are free to assign another word to that other sense
(like 'sometimes' for temporal possibility, or 'may' for the extensional
version). The choice of words is to some extent arbitrary, though we try to
keep close to the more frequent idiom; but the underlying conceptual
distinctions are in any case not open to choice.
This also seems to be Hintikka's thrust. He contrasts 'basic meanings',
which are used as 'explanatory models', and 'residual meanings', which are
modifications of the former by various factors. He mentions as an example, how
a double negation may in practise convey hesitation or uncertainty, or signal
diffidence, or express irony. I will not review his discussion in more detail:
the purpose is served.
However, I want to object parenthetically, once again, to the
consideration of 'epistemic' relations as types of modality. For me, knowledge
and belief are not the primary parameters underlying modality (logical or
otherwise): it is phenomenal appearance
and their seeming credibilities, which structure our logical intuitions
and modal concepts. Epistemic relations are legitimate objects of study for
logical science, but they are not modalities: they do not fit the 'statistical
model' which differentiate modalities, nor serve as singular cases for the
plural constructs.
They may indeed take the place of modalities in everyday discourse, but
their meanings are not equivalent. 'I know so and so' may well imply that so
and so has been found true in my context or absolutely necessary, but it is
not a qualification of the being of the appearances at hand; an extraneous
relation of them to their observer is juxtaposed. The additional information
may well be valuable, but it is incidental; the focus is on the Subject and
his consciousness, instead of only on their Object.
The role of epistemic logic, in logic as a whole, is therefore not as
fundamental as that of proper modalities; it is a tributary field, and it is
no accident that it has arisen in our science rather late in the proceedings
and with great difficulties.
The attempt to bypass philosophical issues, and deal with modality in a
limited framework of 'just logic', is either naive or a self-imposed tunnel
vision. What becomes clear, is that the
issues of modality pervade philosophy, since its inception. Most
philosophical issues have something to do with modality, one way or the other.
This is well brought out in a 1976 paper by Hintikka, with the tantalizing
title of Gaps in the Great Chain of
Being (Knuuttila, 1-17).
In it, in the way of a commentary on a book by Arthur Lovejoy (who
coined the key phrase), he traces the history of 'the idea that all
possibilities are eventually realized', which is known as 'the Principle of
Plenitude', showing how it has taken on different meanings in different
cultural and philosophical contexts. So doing, Hintikka demonstrates his
pretty clear grasp of the various types of modality, and how the emphasis has
shifted from one type to the other across time.
According to Hintikka, apparently with reference to the famous
sea-fight problem, Aristotle subscribed to this principle, at least
ontologically. In natural modality,
plenitude would mean that all potentialities either have been, are or will
sooner or later be actualized: a general inevitability of actualization. (I am
personally not convinced that Aristotle had such deterministic opinions, but
we will let it pass.) Among later philosophers, Hobbes affirmed such a view,
Liebniz denied it.
But the argument behind the belief in plenitude being 'how can a
possibility prove its mettle — its reality — except by being realized in
time?' — its significance is especially epistemological. In
logical modality, plenitude would signify that whatever we but conceive,
has a past, present or future correspondent in reality. That is how, we are
told, Thomas Aquinas interpreted the argument, as a result of his 'kind of
empiricist epistemology', which required that 'in order for us to receive
"true" concepts, they must… already be exemplified in antecedent
reality'.
Additionally, René Descartes' statement that 'matter takes on,
successively, all the forms it is capable [of]',
is interpreted by Hintikka as an extensional
version of plenitude. He argues, 'if all possible species are always realized,
we have a doctrine of the permanence of species'; or alternatively, 'if all
potential kinds of beings will sooner or later emerge… we have a doctrine of
infinite evolution'. With reference G.E.
Moore's discussion, in this century, of the idea that the 'goodness' in
some things is identical with the things themselves — Hintikka also proposes
a temporal interpretation of
plenitude: 'whatever happens always, happens necessarily'. I will comment on
these topics presently.
Hintikka's main purpose in these and other examples, is to show how an
issue traverses history, taking on different shapes as the 'conceptual
environment' changes. His thesis is that the 'hidden ambiguities' in ideas
like the principle of plenitude, make them excellent reflectors of the
varieties of philosophical outlooks, serving as analytical vehicles for
historians.
Thus, he points out how, as of the Renaissance, the 'gradual widening
of what counts as possible' caused a shift in the concept of compulsory
realization of all possibilities. At the time of Aristotle, and up until the
Middle Ages, the realms of the naturally possible and the logically possible
were more or less equal in extent, so that these concepts could be confused.
However, as of the Renaissance, when social and technological developments and
intellectual imagination expanded tremendously, 'the richness of the range of
possibilities' (in every sense) was highlighted.
In one respect, the new optimism could be interpreted as meaning that,
not only was more feasible and therefore more was conceivable, but also
because more was conceivable, more was feasible. But, on another level, the
rates of change were different, so that in the last analysis, more was
conceivable than was feasible. For this reason, I say (and Hintikka seems to
have this view), the question of whether possibilities are bound to be
realized, changed sense: from a nature-oriented one, to a more extreme
imagination-oriented one.
Kant's position on the topic is ambivalent, according to Hintikka; but
he argues that if it is the mind's structure which ultimately limits human
experience, as Kant suggests, then a different structure could well 'in
principle' reveal a different range of possibilities, and no structure,
unlimited possibilities. He points out that there is no 'independently defined
range of possibilities'.
In any case, this argument (though somewhat circular) is interesting,
not only because it highlights the epistemological subtext of possibility, but
because it shows that if the possibilities are infinite, logical and natural
modality issues fuse into one. Enough of history. Hintikka's paper clearly
shows that modality issues may be found at the center of many of the most
fundamental issues of philosophy.
Today, the principle of plenitude is supposedly not taken seriously by
most thinkers. But anyway, let me make my own positions on some of the issues
raised above clear.
First, logical science cannot presume to make any extrapolations like
'all possibilities are eventually realized'. Ab-initio,
as is evidenced by the fact that some people believe otherwise, we must if
possible make formal allowance for
the eventuality of the opposite thesis, otherwise philosophers would be
deprived of a language with which to discuss the issue at all. Thus, the issue
is not of concern to formal logic as such; for us, the concept of
inevitability of realization is a legitimate object of study, which may or may
not eventually be found to be a null-class.
Personally, I have no doubt in the existence of some noninevitable
actualizations (referring to natural modality), since I believe in the
existence of free will (though not in purely material indeterminism,
incidentally). Discussion of free will, or spontaneity more broadly, belongs
in a work on aetiology, but I have already mentioned how it can be formally
introduced into logic (see ch. 34.1). Similarly, for me, the realm of the
logically possible is in principle greater than the realm of the naturally
possible (though there may well be potentialities that we never get to even
conceive), since we seem able to imagine fictions, and if everything was true,
contradictions would arise. These are also the views which seem balanced and
sensible to most people.
In a purely deterministic world, a given piece of clay would either be
bound to become a pot sometimes or be bound to never become one; but in a
world with free will, a piece of clay may remain forever only potentially a
pot. In formal modal logic, we express this in the doctrines of opposition and
compounding of modal propositions. For instance, a never actualized potential
is signified by the compatibility and conjunctions of Ip
and Ec (that is, 'some X can be Y' and 'no X is ever Y'). Similarly,
with reference to imagination.
Secondly, note the intrusion of the concept of time in the generic
statement 'all possibilities are eventually realized'. In natural and temporal
modality, the time involved is that framing the events themselves;
whereas, in logical modality, the time-frame is how
soon we become conscious of the events, which may themselves be perfectly
static. Extensional modality has no
inherent time-frame, though we tend to apply a chronology to it, with
reference to the sequence in which we become aware of different instances (see
ch. 22.3).
The plenitude principle can indeed be conceptually applied to natural
and logical forms of conditioning, but it has no equivalent in temporal or
extensional forms of conditioning. 'This X is sometimes Y' already formally
implies the temporal actualization of some 'this X is Y', and, likewise
'some X are Y' formally implies the extensional instancing of some 'this X is
Y'. Since the implied singular is in either case an actuality, it is a
redundancy to raise the plenitude issue concerning them.
We can indeed ask, ex-post-facto,
whether these implied actualities or instances arose with natural
inevitability or otherwise, but there is no equivalent concept of temporal or
extensional 'inevitability'. In contrast, 'this X can be Y' or 'this X might
be Y' do not formally require that 'this X is Y' be ever actual or true (or,
at least, in their case, the point is at issue). But even with regard to
logical plenitude, the 'inevitability' of realization involved is not itself
strictly a logical modality, but a natural one: it is the natural necessity
that we come to know the facts
concerned.
With regard to the Cartesian claim mentioned earlier. It could be
interpreted naturally: the potentialities in any individual (and therefore for
the species as a whole) must all eventually be actualized; or logically: the
conceivable properties can in principle all be assumed to exist objectively,
and perhaps will inevitably all be directly known by someone someday. But in
any case, these are not purely extensional propositions, contrary to Hintikka's
analysis.
Likewise, the interpretation of G.E. Moore's discussion by Hintikka, in
terms of 'what happens always, happens necessarily', is neither relevant to
the Moore issue, nor does it formally constitute a temporal modality
application of the plenitude principle. The relation of goodness as such to
the entities, states, or motions, of matter or mind, which it characterizes,
is a form-content relation. The things which produce goodness as such in the
world, do not have to themselves be instances of it; that is, 'X causes
Y' does not imply 'X is Y'. As for
the unrelated extrapolation from always to necessarily, it does not fit the
bill of 'inevitable actualization'; taken dynamically to mean determinism, it
would be a natural modality proposition, and taken statically to mean
implication, it would be a logical modality proposition.
Thus, in conclusion, there is in any case no generic principle of
plenitude. There are only specialized situations in which such a principle
might be discussed. One additional remark: none of the above discussions focus
on the logic of 'acquisition and loss of powers', which, like the logic of
'modalities of actualization', represents a dynamic complication of static
modal logic. I have not attempted to work these logics out in detail in the
present treatise, but it should not be too difficult.
Thirdly, the historic discussions of modality confuse two issues. One,
is defining modality and its forms, and working out their deductive
properties. Two, is determining how we induce
modality for specific contents. The argument 'how can possibility be known to
exist, except through its actual manifestations?' at the outset limits us to
perception, and ignores the very conceptual methods which allow its
formulation.
The inductive problem, of predicting possibilities indirectly,
has never clearly been differentiated. As far as I can see, my effort to
formalize the complexities of modal induction is completely original, not only
in its specific findings, but in at all
having raised the issue. For this reason, many of the queries raised by
past philosophers have become obsolete: they henceforth belong to pure logic.
Enough said. The wide range of mutual dependencies between modal logic
and philosophy has been amply demonstrated. I do not propose to try answering
all the question raised (and why not solve the world's problems while at it!).
In any case, the literature research effected in this chapter has served to
show the level of knowledge (and the blank areas) other authors have attained,
with regard to tropology.
|